Thursday, July 10, 2014

Robert Nozick's Argument against Wealth Redistribution


Wealth inequality has existed to some degree in every free society known to man. In the United States of America in particular, the current disparity between the richest and the poorest is astronomical. Many people today have argued that it is unethical for some individuals to accumulate so much wealth while others have barely enough to keep themselves alive. It is the responsibility of the state, according to these welfare economists, to maximize net happiness by distributing wealth from the richest individuals to the poorest. Some have argued that these redistributions should be in the form of taxation, while others of more revolutionary persuasion advocate the appropriation of others’ holdings by force. Regardless of how it is attempted, wealth redistribution of any kind is patently immoral, according to the philosophy of Robert Nozick (1938-2002). Nozick is considered by many, including myself, to be one of the most influential libertarian thinkers. His 1974 book, Anarchy, State, and Utopia is a phenomenal text that sets the groundwork for much of modern libertarian philosophy[1]. In Chapter Seven of Anarchy, State, and Utopia, entitled Distributive Justice, Nozick makes what I believe to be the soundest argument against wealth redistribution.

According to Nozick, someone’s entitlement to a holding is justified only if it was voluntarily transferred to them. Acquiring something by trade, by purchase, by gift, or on loan is a justifiable claim to a possession, but if something is acquired by extortion or thievery, then that holding is not just and Nozick would argue that in a free society, such an injustice would need to be rectified. Nozick’s Entitlement Theory is historical. If the sequence of events leading up to someone acquiring an object is justifiable, then so is the acquisition. If, for example, a burglar stole a television and then sold it to a friend, and that friend gave me the television as a gift, I would still not be entitled to the television since it was first acquired by unjust means. Therefore, as long as a given distribution of wealth came about by just means, then that distribution, according to Nozick is also just, regardless of how unequal the distribution may be. Those who complain about wealth inequality must understand that the current distribution of wealth has come about through voluntary exchange and the laws of supply and demand acting throughout history. Even though some people are extraordinarily wealthy and some live in destitute poverty, does not entail that anybody (especially the government) can claim possession of another’s holding for the purpose of redistribution.  

A person can only be entitled to a holding if he acquired it by just means. To illustrate this point, Robert Nozick presents what has come to be known as the Wilt Chamberlain Argument[2]. Nozick asks us to imagine a society with an egalitarian distribution of wealth, which he calls D1. Now imagine that in this society, Wilt Chamberlain puts on a basketball game and charges spectators twenty-five cents each to watch him play. Assuming that one million people decide to watch him play basketball, then Chamberlain would make a quarter of a million dollars from this transaction and all the spectators would be out one quarter. Nozick calls this new distribution of wealth D2. Even though the new distribution in D2 is extremely unequal compared to D1, D2 is still morally justifiable if all the spectators voluntarily chose to pay Wilt Chamberlain the quarter. In D2, Chamberlain would be far wealthier than anyone else, but he would still be entitled to every quarter given to him. This example shows how a non-egalitarian distribution is still justifiable even if a great disparity exists between the poorest and the richest. Inequality is not immoral as long as the transactions that brought about such an inequality were themselves moral and not coerced.

100-point games played and 20, 000 women laid

Nozick argues that a society with an egalitarian distribution of wealth is not only immoral, but impossible, since such a society would have to arrest all transactions between consenting individuals. Nozick writes,

“The general point illustrated by the Wilt Chamberlain example is that no end-sate principle or distributional patterned principle of justice can be continuously realized without continuous interference with people’s lives... To maintain a pattern, one must either continually interfere to stop people from transferring resources as they wish to, or continually interfere to take from persons resources that others for some reason chose to transfer to them.”[3]


Even if a society could somehow redistribute all wealth in accordance with an egalitarian principle, the distribution would not remain equal for very long. As the Chamberlain argument demonstrates, people are always going to voluntarily engage in transactions with others. These transactions are naturally going to make some people extraordinarily wealthy, and other people, by their own undoing, extremely poor. The problem with welfare economics is that it assumes there to be some ideal state of wealth distribution that would make everyone better off. It is an end-state philosophy. Reality is not composed of end-state distributions however, but of continuous transactions in which resources exchange hands between those who are entitled to them. To propose that there is some ideal distribution of wealth is therefore absurd because it completely discounts how the current state of wealth inequality came about. In order to impose a given distribution of wealth, the state would have to use force against anyone who did not act in accordance with the ideal distribution, which would not only be in violation of individual rights, but would also entail an enormous waste of time and effort.


As we can see, there is nothing inherently wrong with wealth inequality, regardless of what socialists and welfare advocates would have you believe. In a free society, the most talented and business-savvy individuals are bound to accumulate wealth, whereas those with no particular skills will not. As long as those wealthy people have earned their money through voluntary transactions, then they are entitled to every penny of it. It would be unethical, according to Nozick, for any Robin Hood-like character to redistribute the holdings of others on the basis that a current distribution is unequal. A free society must respect the life, liberty, and property of all.





[1] http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nozick-political/#MinStaVerIndAna
[2] Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia, pg. 161
[3] Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia, pg. 163